RENEWAMERICA.us  -  Home  -  News  -  Columns  -  Alan Keyes column  -  Keyes Archives  -  Message Board


Judicial review and executive responsibility

March 28, 2005
Alan Keyes




Despite action by Congress to create an opportunity for the federal courts to review and correct the violation of Terri Schiavo's most basic rights, the latest effort to prevent her judicially sanctioned murder by starvation appears to be headed for failure.

This is just the latest, and the most poignantly tragic instance of judicial abuse tending to corrupt and destroy the moral fabric of our nation.

Despite the outward appearance of deliberation, what we witness now as an ongoing feature of the conduct of the judiciary at every level amounts to a judicial riot, in which judges and justices take it upon themselves to disregard the prerogatives of the other branches in order to assert an exclusive and tyrannical control of public standards and conduct.

Why is this happening?

The root of the problem is the abuse of the power of judicial review. This played a role in the Schiavo case, when the Florida State Supreme Court declared unconstitutional the Florida legislature's attempt to authorize protection for Terri Schiavo's continued access to nutrition.

But in a constitutional system based on checks and balances, one branch can run riot only if some other branch fails to exert the power necessary to constrain its actions within constitutional bounds.

This means that the rise of judicial tyranny represents a failure elsewhere in the government.

Now we know that in the Schiavo case, both the Florida and the national legislatures exerted themselves in an effort to secure her basic right to life. They failed because the judiciary has the power to invalidate their actions, either in application or through the power of judicial review.




In the end, the constraint of judicial abuse is especially the responsibility of the executive branch of government, since the executive has both the opportunity and the obligation to act without the interference of the judiciary, provided that in doing so he consults the political will of the legislative power.

Until and unless the people elected to wield executive power in our national and state governments recognize and act upon this responsibility, the judiciary will go unchecked, destroying the balance of power among the branches and with it our system of free, representative self-government.

The essay that follows reviews the thinking behind the separation of powers argument that substantiates this understanding of the current crisis of judicial abuse. Though it focuses on the Schiavo case as a critical and currently urgent instance of this crisis, it has a bearing as well on the judicial assault on marriage in Massachusetts, and the general judicial assault on public piety taking place through the nation.

The implication of the argument is clear: We cannot pin our hopes on new judges to end this long era of judicial usurpation. We need chief executives with the understanding, articulateness, and courage to assert the executive prerogative that will remind the judges that under our constitutional principles, neither the judges, nor the legislatures, nor the executives may claim permanent supremacy — rather it is the constitutional power of the people that is superior to them all.

The meaning of separation

These days, the term separation of powers is used as if it refers to a merely administrative division of decision-making responsibility. This ignores the fact that the Founders, and the philosophers such as Montesquieu from whom they drew inspiration, presented separation as a substantive requirement of free government.

As Madison wrote in Federalist 47, "The accumulation of all powers, legislative, executive and judiciary, in the same hands, whether of one, a few or many, and where hereditary, self-appointed, or elective, may justly be pronounced the very definition of tyranny."

No one of the branches of government can have supreme and exclusive decision-making authority, because no one branch can, by itself, safely be allowed to exercise the whole power of government in any circumstance. The legislature makes the laws, but is powerless to execute them. The judiciary can decide cases in light of the law, but has no authority either to execute decisions once taken, or control the content of the law. The executive has the exclusive power of direct action, but no lawful authority to act apart from the provisions of the laws and the constitution, or the specific judgments of the judiciary.

In order to be separate, the branches must be independent. Obviously, this does not mean that in any case, a branch can simply act on its own authority — but it does mean that in every case, each branch must act on the basis of its own will and judgment.

The branches are subject to the laws and the constitution, but they are not directly subject to either of the other branches. The legislature, for example, cannot simply dictate to the courts the outcome of any particular case. Neither, however can the courts dictate to the legislature the content of any law. The legislature can establish programs and mandates for executive action, but cannot simply dictate to the executive the particular action to be taken in pursuance of its legislation. Because each branch substantively controls the power vested in it, the other branches cannot simply dictate the use of that power.

In the division of the whole power of government established by the constitution, each branch has some ability to prevent or interfere with the actions of the others. This is an inherent consequence of the division of government power. The laws passed by the legislature will be of no reliable effect if the executive refuses to enforce them or the courts refuse to apply their provisions to the particular cases that arise from them. Similarly, the executive may decide to act, but cannot sustain the cooperation and support of the citizenry (including those who comprise the enforcing arms of executive power) if the legislature refuses legal sanction to its action. The court may judge, but must do so without effect once the people realize that its actions have no basis in law, and/or the executive offers its opposition or simply withholds its cooperation.




None of the branches can effectively operate without the acquiescence or cooperation of at least one of the others. Differently construed, we could say that no one of the branches can sustain its authority when faced with the united opposition of the remaining branches. This aspect of the U.S. Constitution reflects the essence of law itself, which is a coercive rule made by and for the sake of the whole community which applies to the individuals who are in it.

The legislature, chosen by and representing the will of the whole people, makes the rule. The judiciary, by its judgments in particular cases, applies the rule. The executive, chosen by the people, represents its coercive force. In the absence of any one of these elements, there is, properly speaking, no law.

The separation of powers doctrine, by placing each of these elements under a discrete authority, effectively precludes the existence of law unless by some means all three of these elements are brought into play. Because by itself no one branch has the authority to make the law, it can never be forgotten that this authority rests ultimately with the people. They have constituted the government. All three branches of government are subject to their will, as expressed in the Constitution, and through laws made pursuant to its provisions, and carried out by their constitutionally selected representatives.

Negation and cooperation

Because our constitutions give each branch control over the power of government it represents, the separation of powers works to assure that those who comprise the government cannot act as if their will is the law. What one branch says, another may negate, thereby withholding from its pronouncement one of the essential attributes of law.

By withholding cooperation, for example, the executive may deprive both legislative acts and judicial decisions of the force of law.[1] But without coercive force, there is no law, properly speaking.

By the same token, if the judiciary refuses to apply the law in particular cases, its provisions and penalties will not be applied to individuals, the executive has no authorization to act with respect to them, and the legislative will have no particular effect.

Obviously, if the legislature has provided no pretext of legislation, except where the safety and security of the Constitution or the people clearly require it, neither the judiciary nor the executive can claim lawful authority for their decisions or actions.

Isn't this a recipe for paralysis? Why isn't constitutional government hamstrung by the mutual negation of the branches? In the U.S. Constitution provision is made against this paralysis by giving each branch a role in the superintendence of the others, thus acknowledging that the existence of the law depends on their cooperation.

A president, for example, who acts in simple disregard of the laws passed by the legislature is subject to impeachment and removal by the Congress. The trial of impeachment, however, requires the active involvement and cooperation of the federal judiciary, in the person of the Chief Justice of the Supreme Court.

Without the cooperation of the Chief Justice, a trial of impeachment cannot go forward. Should the move for impeachment result from some transient passion in the legislature, opposition from the Court would check its initial fury.

Of course, if the legislature is determined to act, it might remove the obstacle by impeachment and removal of the opposing Justice, but since the president must appoint his successor, such action would shift but not resolve the impasse. The need for cooperation in fact and principle ought to provide a practical incentive for each of the branches to secure, in any given instance, at least the passive acquiescence of one of its coequals.

There is of course no guarantee that even with this incentive, paralysis and inaction will be avoided, but some degree of constraint upon government action must be the intended purpose of a frame of government whose ultimate aim is to forestall tyranny and protect the freedom of the people, which is to say the right of the people to govern their own affairs.

When situations arise in which no effective cooperation can be achieved between the branches, the determination of power shifts into the hands of the people as a whole, who by their election of different persons to the legislature or the executive can determine the balance of power one way or another, if they please. If it so happens that the people are not sufficiently united in their views, lawful government action is precluded — which in effect represents a decision by the people to leave matters to be determined by themselves, by their respective private capacities.

These reflections clearly imply that the separation of powers is not a passive delineation of decision-making responsibility. It is, instead, the constitutional consequence of the overall objective of free government — to prevent the permanent consolidation of government power under the control of one concerted will and judgment; i.e., to prevent tyranny. Separation is therefore not simply a doctrine established by constitutional fiat, but a goal to be achieved, one that must be respected if the people are to remain free.

The attainment of this goal requires that each branch of government actively assert and sustain its independent will and judgment, while at the same time showing a prudent regard for the mutual interdependence and cooperation required for effective government action. It also requires that the people, whom Hamilton calls the "natural guardians of the Constitution" (Federalist 16), hold their representatives accountable for the performance of their duty in this regard, since persistent failure in this duty represents the destruction of self-government.




The power of constitutional review

As a matter of logic and fact, the Founders assumed that the judicial branch would be the most vulnerable participant in the dynamic interaction that establishes the substantive separation of powers. In Federalist 78 Hamilton writes:

"Whoever attentively considers the different departments of power must perceive, that, in a government in which they are separated from each other, the judiciary, from the nature of its functions, will always be the least dangerous to the political rights of the Constitution; because it will be least in a capacity to annoy or injure them. The executive not only dispenses the honors, but holds the sword of the community. The legislature not only commands the purse, but prescribes the rules by which the duties and rights of every citizen are to be regulated. The judiciary, on the contrary, has no influence over either the sword or the purse; no direction either of the strength or of the wealth of the society; and can take no active resolution whatever. It may truly be said to have neither force nor will, but merely judgment; and must ultimately depend upon the aid of the executive arm even for the efficacy of its judgments."[2]

This argument is clear and on the face of it quite logical, but only on the assumption that the decisions of the judiciary do not absolutely override the other branches. Obviously, if the decision of the judge automatically binds the executive and legislative branches, it would make no sense to say that the judiciary has no influence over "either the sword or the purse." Its decisions would necessarily determine the disposition of the one and the other.

The assumption that the judiciary has neither force nor will must be premised on the notion that neither the legislature nor the executive is simply subject to the dictates of the judiciary. The other branches may check the judgment of the courts when it comes to the disposition of that power of government constitutionally allocated to their control. As we have observed already, that check consists in the prerogative of each branch to take a stand on constitutional grounds, and say no, refusing to submit to another in the use of its constitutionally separate authority.

This clear logic meets with resistance in our day because of the general acceptance of judicial review, what Hamilton in the same paper refers to as "the rights of the courts to pronounce legislative acts void, because contrary to the constitution."

The concept of judicial review has been used as the basis for a doctrine of judicial supremacy, whereby both the legislature and the executive must simply submit to the judgments of the judiciary, which claims to have the sole authority to interpret the Constitution.

Though unquestioned today, this notion met with objections during the debates over the Constitution, as Hamilton acknowledges, "from an imagination that the doctrine would imply a superiority of the judiciary to the legislative power." (Federalist 78)

In the paragraph that follows this acknowledgment, Hamilton argues that "There is no position which depends on clearer principles, than that every act of a delegated authority, contrary to the tenor of the commission under which it is exercised, is void. No legislative act, therefore, contrary to the Constitution, can be valid. To deny this, would be to affirm, that the deputy is greater than his principal; that the servant is above his master; that the representatives of the people are superior to the people themselves; that men acting by virtue of powers, may do not only what their powers do not authorize, but what they forbid."

In light of this reasoning, Hamilton quite logically maintains that when the judges compare the provisions of any law to the Constitution, "If there should happen to be an irreconcilable variance between the two, that which has the superior obligation and validity ought, of course, to be preferred; or in other words, the Constitution ought to be preferred to the statute, the intention of the people to the intention of their agents."

He continues, "Nor does this conclusion by any means suppose a superiority of the judicial to the legislative power. It only supposes that the power of the people is superior to both."

It is clear that in the exercise of its powers, the judicial branch cannot avoid the situation Hamilton describes, any more than it can avoid — as he later points out — the need to choose between contradictory laws, or contradictory elements of a particular law. In order to pass judgment in a particular case, the judges must decide which law will govern, and Hamilton's argument as to the primacy of the Constitution makes sense on the face of it.

But advocates of judicial supremacy overlook the fact that his argument from logic and principle applies with equal force to the other branches of government in the exercise of the powers allocated to them.

If, for example, the chief executive confronts a decision from the bench that conflicts with constitutional provisions as to his powers and prerogatives, or those of the legislature, or those of the people, he must give primacy to the Constitution, as the legislature must in a similar situation of conflict.

The Constitution supreme

Each branch must conduct its affairs in light of its responsibility to the Constitution, and indeed those persons who comprise the branches are all of them sworn to do so. Thus, while Hamilton's argument establishes the rationale for judicial review of legislative and executive actions, it also establishes the rationale for executive and legislative review of judicial decisions when those decisions affect legislative and executive responsibilities to, and for, the integrity of the Constitution.

But doesn't the possibility of executive and legislative review of judicial actions fly in the face of the fact, noted by Hamilton in Federalist 78 that "the interpretation of the laws is the proper and peculiar province of the courts." If disagreement arises between the branches as to the import of the Constitution or the laws, doesn't the judicial branch have the prerogative of deciding what shall be the authoritative interpretation?




In the ordinary course of affairs, this must be and is taken for granted, as Hamilton recognizes when he notes that "to avoid an arbitrary discretion in the courts, it is indispensable that they should be bound down by strict rules and precedents, which serve to define and point out their duty in every particular case." This implies that, though abuses are possible, the judiciary, by means of rules and precedents, acts as the watchdog of its own discretion.

If we accept this as proof of the ultimate supremacy of judicial discretion in every circumstance, however, the consequence must be the utter subversion of the separate identity of the other branches of government.

Every proper human action involves the faculty of judgment. Laws cannot be made, except the legislators make judgments about what aims are proper and attainable, what means are suitable and proportionate to the desired ends, and so forth. Similarly, no executive action can be taken without regard to the circumstances of action — whether the times, the available resources, the legally established priorities, and the actual details of a given situation allow for effective action.

In this sense, though the judicial power of government may be vested in a single branch, the exercise of judgment is inseparable from the operation of all the branches. If in the exercise of executive power, the judicial branch may without constraint substitute its judgment for that of the executive, it subsumes the executive power, and so too with respect to the legislature and the legislative power.

Unchecked by potential opposition from the other branches, judicial power necessarily becomes judicial tyranny. Since this substantively defeats the whole aim and purpose of the separation of powers, we must reject any understanding of separation that leads to this result.

Yet this is exactly what must result if we accept the arguments of the judicial supremacists. The Constitution, as it embodies the superior expression of the will of the people, supersedes the momentary will of their agents or representatives. Since any and every dispute over law and policy must be construed in light of constitutional provisions, anyone who can claim to be the ultimate arbiter of their meaning claims ultimate authority over the government as a whole. Yet by arrogating to itself authority over the government as a whole, the judiciary secures for itself a position superior to the Constitution itself, which is to say superior to the will of the people as the ultimate authority on which its legitimacy depends.

Thus in effect, the judicial supremacists overthrow the Constitution, acting much as the Grand Viziers of those Moorish potentates in Spain, who, by securing the opportunity to be the sole interpreter of the sovereign's will, substituted their authority for his, making themselves the rulers.[3]

It follows from these considerations that, just as we must distinguish between substantive and procedural due process, so we must observe the distinction between substantive and administrative separation of powers. As a matter of administrative structure, the judicial power is vested in the judicial branch. As a matter of substantive constitutional integrity, each branch must retain and exercise an independent faculty of judgment, especially with respect to its own constitutional rights and responsibilities.[4]

What must be obvious on the face of it, moreover, is that matters of substantive separation are not justiciable, meaning to say they cannot ultimately be decided by the courts. As Hamilton observes in Federalist 80, "No man ought certainly to be a judge in his own case, or in any cause in respect to which he has the least interest or bias." We must assume that the judiciary will be biased in favor of its own power, and its own judgment concerning the nature and extent of that power.

This does not of course mean that the courts may have no opinion on this subject. In fact, when unchallenged by another branch of government, their opinion will in any case prevail. It does mean that the other branches must retain the right to challenge and reject the opinion of the judiciary when it conflicts with their own considered judgment especially with respect to their own constitutional rights, responsibilities and obligations.




The executive's role

Given the importance to liberty of the fundamental constitutional principle that is at stake, and the potentially grave consequences of carelessness or neglect in its regard, we ought to proceed with great care in our application of the foregoing reasoning and conclusions.

Yet we must urgently forge ahead, as these days we encounter practically at every turn some new evidence that the failure to appreciate them has already allowed developments that represent the tyrannical consolidation of governmental powers the Founders rightly feared and rejected.

Contrary to their expectation, however, the greatest threat to constitutional liberty, and indeed to the very fabric of free society as a whole, has come from the judiciary, the branch of government Hamilton regarded as the weakest, and the least likely to achieve tyrannical control.

From education to prayer to critical decisions affecting the most fundamental rights of life and public conscience, our courts at every level now claim the right to impose their views, as law, not only on individual citizens, but on both the other branches of government.

They have taken over school systems, dismantled public monuments, and threatened to subvert the substance of institutions such as marriage, whose character has until now been unquestionably determined by the legislative, not the judicial power.

We must bear in mind that our constitutions, at both the federal and the state level, are all based on republican principles — which is to say, on the idea that laws are properly made by legislatures comprised of the elected representatives of the people, and which act as such only by vote of a constitutionally prescribed majority.

If and when the opinions of judges, without proper basis in our laws or constitutions, may claim to become law, the republican principle has been subverted, and with it the right of the people to representative self-government.

It is also clear that, unless the people mean to abdicate their role as the ultimate source of authority for our constitutional arrangements, they cannot accept the notion that judges may indulge in any constitutional fancies they please, without regard to reason, common sense, or the moral sense and conscience of the people.

When a substantial majority of the people regards a judicial determination as an unlawful abuse or usurpation of power, therefore, they are not obliged to acquiesce out of respect for the mere form of legal judgment.

As we have seen, the legitimate argument for judicial review does not "suppose a superiority of the judicial to the legislative power. It only supposes that the power of the people is superior to both." The question is, when faced with judicial abuse and usurpation, how can the people, by lawful and constitutional means, assert their superiority?

In Federalist 79, Hamilton observes that "the precautions for this [judicial] responsibility are comprised in the article respecting impeachments."

It would make sense to suppose that consistent abuse of the judicial power in a way that subverts the integrity of constitutional self-government would rouse public feeling and lead to action on the part of the representatives of the people.

When he discusses impeachment in Federalist 65, Hamilton says of the court required for this purpose that "the subjects of its jurisdiction are those offences which proceed from the misconduct of public men, or in other words, from the abuse or violation of some public trust. They are of a nature which may with peculiar propriety be denominated political, as they relate chiefly to injuries done immediately to the society itself."

It is hard to conceive of a more weighty public trust than the power to review the application, in particular cases, of the laws, and to void acts of the legislature deemed inconsistent with the provisions of fundamental law as embodied in our constitutions.

Impeachment offers itself as the natural remedy against judges who insist on assaulting the liberty of the people by unjustifiably usurping the prerogatives of their representative law-making bodies, or ignoring constitutional provisions intended to secure the rights of the people.

Unfortunately, in the present day, common sense has fallen prey to the self-serving arguments of the legal profession to the effect that impeachment is intended to remedy only statutory, not constitutional, violations.

We are told that judges cannot be called to account for the destructive constitutional effect of their decisions, only for their petty criminal conduct.

Crimes of limited effect may therefore be acted upon, but those political crimes that tend to destroy free society as a whole must not only be ignored, but treated with the respect due to the law. This pernicious illogic may appeal to the instincts of would-be Machiavellians, but it's hard to see how it makes sense for a free people intent on remaining free.

A case of judicial abuse

Still, until more politicians rediscover the clear common sense of Hamilton's understanding of impeachment, it will continue to be an ineffective, indeed a non-existent, recourse against practitioners of judicial tyranny. Is there no other?

We may see the answer most clearly in the context of a well-known situation in which the issue of judicial prerogative and the separation of powers has played a critical role.




In the State of Florida, a circuit court judge decided, despite a challenge from her parents, that Terri Schiavo's husband should be permitted to remove the tube through which she has been receiving nutrition after brain damage left her in a helpless condition.

The decision to starve her to death aroused a firestorm of protest in Florida and around the nation, leading the Florida legislature to pass a law specifically intended to prevent implementation of the judge's decision.

The legislature acted in support of Gov. Jeb Bush, who felt that the decision to starve Terri Schiavo to death constituted a violation of her basic right to life, a right specifically protected under the Florida state constitution (Article I, Section 2).

Thus, both the legislature and the chief executive agreed in the view that the judiciary's action violated the Florida constitution. The Florida judiciary disagreed.

Eventually, the Florida State Supreme Court declared the legislature's act invalid, mainly on the grounds that it violated the principle of the separation of powers by encroaching upon the decision-making prerogatives of the judicial branch.

But if the actions of the Florida legislature and the state's duly elected chief executive are representative of the people (and as a matter of constitutional principle they must be so regarded), a constitutional majority of the people agreed in the view that the Florida judiciary acted in violation of the state's constitution.[5] So we must ask: If, as Hamilton maintains, the argument for judicial review rests ultimately on the superiority of the people's constitutional will over that of subordinate delegated authorities, can the Florida judiciary invoke the power of judicial review to thwart the effort of their representatives to assert and safeguard their understanding of the constitution?

In all fairness, however, that is not exactly what the Florida Supreme Court did. It simply regarded the legislature's action as an attempt to overturn the judgment of the court in a particular case. The prerogative to decide particular cases, of course, belongs to the judiciary. If the legislature can, after the fact, overturn particular judgments by law, the legislative power would absorb the judicial power, destroying the separation of powers required by our constitutional principles. Any legislative action that simply reverses judicial judgment in a particular case is on the face of it unconstitutional.[6]

But the Florida chief executive shared the legislature's view. As governor, Jeb Bush represents a separate government power, a distinct and independent governmental authority. As the state's chief executive, he is sworn to uphold the Florida state constitution, an obligation that necessarily includes taking such actions as are necessary to preserve, protect, and defend the integrity of its provisions. If by some circumstance he becomes aware of a situation in which that integrity is being damaged, he is bound by his oath to act in its defense.

If, for example, he were notified that a court-sanctioned, racially-motivated lynching was taking place across the street from the state house, he would be oath bound as chief executive to intervene to prevent the violation of constitutional right and integrity.

Even if a racist judge had ordered the hanging, as chief executive he would have a responsibility to the Florida constitution making it impossible for him to respect the judge's order, however well decked out in formal judicial garb.




In such a circumstance, if Jeb Bush ignored the constitutional violation and later pleaded that he was respecting the court order, his plea would have no more validity than the plea of Nazi generals that they were only obeying orders.[7]

Indeed, his claim would be more precarious, since the separate and independent status of the executive branch of government is a well known and widely acknowledged element of American constitutional principle.

As Hamilton made clear, judicial review invokes the superiority of the Constitution, as it embodies the permanent will of the people, not the superiority of the judges or the judicial power. Where the exercise of judicial power conflicts with the Constitution's requirements, the Constitution must take precedence.

Of course, some may contend that the executive must be bound by the judiciary's understanding of what is consistent with the Constitution, but this cannot be accepted in a case where the judiciary's opinion conflicts with the executive's deliberate and conscientious view of his own constitutional obligations.

As we have seen above, there can be no separation of power where the judgment of one branch as to its own responsibilities is simply subordinate to the judgment of another. The executive's oath would not in that case fix responsibility for the use or abuse of executive power.

Just as the separation of powers principle precludes legislative efforts to decide particular cases before the judiciary, so it precludes any judicial claim to decide conclusively for the executive how he fulfills the duty to defend the integrity of constitutional self-government, including of course the rights of individual citizens.

This is particularly true when the executive is confronted with a conflict between the will of the people as expressed in an act of the legislature and the opinion of the judiciary that the act is unconstitutional. Just as the judges and justices must follow the Constitution rather than the law, so the executive must follow the Constitution rather than the opinion of the judiciary, if he believes that opinion requires him to go against the Constitution.

To be sure, the judiciary may then declare its opinion that the executive's action is unlawful, but in American constitutional practice the judiciary is not the branch that judges the misconduct of the chief executive.

That prerogative belongs to the legislature. When the legislature and the executive agree on the constitutionality of his actions, the judiciary has no authority whatsoever to charge (i.e., impeach) or try the executive on account of them.

Obviously, this means that no judicial order can be executed against the chief executive if he objects to it.

Supreme authority to act

In the particular case involving Terri Schiavo, some expressed the patently illogical view that Judge Greer's injunction gave a county sheriff the right to resist action by Gov. Bush. But this would mean that by judicial order, a state judge can claim to establish an executive authority superior to the governor of Florida.

However, the Florida constitution makes the governor the supreme executive authority in the state. It also states, in Article 2 Section 3 of the Florida State constitution, that no branch can claim to exercise the powers of another.

On two counts, the judge's claim contradicts the constitution, and is therefore without merit.[8]

Even if the judge claims to be acting according to law, no combination of law and inferior executive authority can supersede the permanent grant of supreme authority to the governor in the constitution. If this were possible, then the judiciary's claimed power of judicial review would also fail, since it is based on the notion that no law is valid that conflicts with the constitution.

Nor can we sustain the argument that the governor's action would violate prohibition against executive exercise of the judiciary's power. If, as chief executive of Florida, Jeb Bush believes that starving Terri Schiavo to death is a violation of her right to life, as recognized in the Florida constitution (Article I, Section 2), he has the same obligation to defend constitutional right as he would in the lynching example.

Unlike the legislature, he would not act to overturn or reverse the action of the judiciary, but in order positively to fulfill his direct constitutional obligation as chief executive, by preventing the destruction of a citizen's most basic constitutional right.

Just as the courts have the initiative when it comes to deciding particular cases, the executive has the initiative when it comes to the actual defense of the constitution and the constitutional rights of the citizens.

If, for example, prior to the invasion of Iraq, the Supreme Court had, in the course of adjudicating a case, issued an injunction against President G. W. Bush forbidding him to order U.S. forces into Iraq, the order would have had no effect on his constitutionally established power as Commander-in Chief, and his sworn duty to defend the country and the Constitution.

Deference to the Court would mean abdicating his authority as Commander-in-Chief, even as, by deferring to Judge Greer, Gov. Jeb Bush abdicates his authority as supreme executive of Florida. Either abdication implies a serious dereliction of duty.

Though it is indispensable for effective government, of course, there are undeniable dangers in the constitutional grant of supreme executive power. However, when the initiative lies with the executive, it is for the people, through their representatives in the legislature, not the judiciary, to safeguard against executive abuses.

If the legislature and the judiciary agree that the executive is abusing his power, the representatives of the people can charge the executive with the violation of law, impeaching and if necessary removing him from office for his actions, with no imputation of damage to the separation of powers.

If on the other hand, the legislature agrees with the executive, as the Florida legislature did in the Terri Schiavo case, it can offer legislative support in his defense against any maneuvers the judiciary may employ to impose its will. In that case, the legislature will be acting to support the executive's defense of the integrity of the constitution, not interfering after the fact with the judiciary's adjudication of a particular case.

Despite his protestations of interest and conscience with respect to the assault on Terri Schiavo's constitutional rights, Jeb Bush has failed to act on his clear and direct responsibility to defend the integrity of Florida's constitution.

Whether from timidity or political calculation, he has pretended that legislative initiative is required to authorize his action, even in the face of consistent proof that the legislature is powerless against a determined and literally ruthless application of judicial prerogative.

As a result, the nation and the world have been witness to the spectacle of the slow, judicially mandated murder of an innocent and helpless woman, while Jeb Bush's actions have given credibility to the patently false impression that the judiciary has any claim whatsoever to executive authority over the chief executive.




His example, and the false but pernicious precedent it offers, threatens the integrity of constitutional government throughout the nation, especially given the natural implication that President Bush tacitly approves of his brother's surrender of executive responsibility.

The law's delay must cost Terri Schiavo her life, which is precisely the reason executive power in America is entrusted to single executives, rather than to plural deliberative bodies.

When time is of the essence, necessity authorizes the executive to safeguard the security of the constitution and the people before citizens and the polity suffer irreversible damage.

Terri Schiavo's survival depends on Gov. Bush's faithful execution of this responsibility, and the survival of American self-government on the willingness of all those in a like position faithfully to execute the duties of their high office.

In times like these, calculating politicians are not good enough. Enlightened statesmen are needed at the helm. God help us if we do not soon choose to find them there.

NOTES:

[1]  "As stated above, the notion of law contains two things; first, that it is a rule of human acts; secondly, that it has coercive power." St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, Question 96, Article 5

[2]  Hamilton shows elsewhere that he understands the ultimate significance of the Executive's power to withhold cooperation from the judiciary. In Federalist 16, as he argues for the necessity of a federal government that can "carry its agency to the persons of the citizens" without assistance from the State governments, he alludes to "the essential difference between a mere non-compliance and a direct and active resistance. If the interposition of the State legislatures be necessary to give effect to a measure of the union, they have only not to act, or to act evasively, and the measure is defeated." Where the judiciary must rely upon the Executive for the execution of its judgments, the same implicit veto power exists, and as Hamilton makes clear it has been left intact in the U.S. Constitution. In Book 11, Chapter 6 of "De L'Esprit Des Lois" Montesquieu recognizes this power as one of the key constituents of legislative power. "J'appelle faculte d'empecher, le droit de rendre nulle une resolution prise par quelque autre; ce qui etoit la puissance des tribuns de Rome. Et quoique celui qui a la faculte d'empecher puisse avoir aussi le droit d'approuver, pour lors cette approbation n'est autre chose qu'une declaration qu'il ne fait point usage de sa faculte d'empecher, et derive de cette faculte." This key aspect of executive power is formally recognized in the U.S. Constitution in the guise of what we call the president's veto power with respect to legislation, which is set up to operate in exactly the fashion Montesquieu describes. It is worth noting that this power is simply a formal recognition of the implicit power the Executive has in any case. The majority required to override the president's veto is, not coincidentally, the same as that required in the U.S. Senate to remove him from office. Thus the constitutional provisions formally and openly recognize what is in any case true of the Executive's power and the constraints upon it. No such formal recognition is given to this power with respect to judicial judgments. This means that its exercise is not a matter of constitutional law, but of Executive discretion, requiring a greater degree of understanding, energy and initiative in the Executive precisely because it is more liable to be challenged by the judiciary. As a matter of simple prudence, the Executive is therefore unlikely to invoke it unless he is sure he has the necessary support in the legislature and among the people to avoid political catastrophe. This is probable only where consistent judicial abuse has tried the patience, and roused the conscience and opposition of the people, and where the ultimate danger it poses to their persons, life or property becomes clear.

[3]  I have yet to encounter anyone who can refute this case against the notion that the judiciary has the exclusive power of constitutional review. Common sense and sound reasoning both support the conclusion that each branch must exercise this power in the course of fulfilling its sworn duty to support, protect, and defend the constitution. Those who doubt that common sense and reasoning can be the basis for a claim of constitutional authority, need to remember that no provision of the U.S. Constitution grants the judiciary power of constitutional review. In Federalist 78 and later in Marbury v. Madison, Hamilton and Marshall establish it by means of common sense reasoning. If this is no basis for the claim of constitutional authority, then the judiciary has no power of judicial review. If it is a proper basis, then sound reasoning may be used to establish the like claim of authority for the other branches. The judiciary is in any case especially dependent on the authority of reason. In order to claim the authority of law, each and every one of their decisions must be shown to have a basis in statutory law or the constitution. Where their decisions simply apply the precise text of the law, this connection is easy to see. Where they must construe the text in order to apply it, reasoning is needed to establish the validity of their construction. In either case, the authority of reasoning is what validates their use of judicial power. Without it, the judiciary would have no authority whatsoever.

[4]  Obviously, though this is the most important area where independent judgment must be reserved, it is not the only one. For example, in times of national emergency, the Executive cannot cede to the judiciary the power to make decisions that affect national security. Nor in any case can the executive cede to the judiciary control of the armed forces of the government, and so forth.

[5]  The Florida State Constitution declares the right to enjoy and defend life to be "inalienable." This term means that it cannot be given away or transferred to another by law. The statute which transfers to Michael Schiavo the authority to make any decision that involves positive action to take Terri Schiavo's life, such as starving her to death, is on the face of it unconstitutional, since it transfers away from her that which cannot constitutionally be transferred by law to another. The Florida Supreme Court eagerly struck down the legislative act intended to save Terri's life, but utterly ignored the constitutional impropriety of the statute that purportedly authorized Michael Schiavo to destroy it. Apparently in Florida today judicial review only applies when it supports evil.

[6]  The Founding generation, through its knowledge and experience of the British constitution, was well aware of the possibility that the legislature, or some part of it, may compose the judiciary. They rejected this arrangement in favor of an independent judiciary.

[7]  He that carries out the sentence of the judge who has condemned an innocent man, if the sentence contains an inexcusable error, he should not obey..." Aquinas, Ibid., Q. 64, Art. 6, Reply to objection 3. As a matter of moral conscience, it is inexcusable to take innocent human life. In the Schiavo case Judge Greer accepts the notion that extreme disability has deprived Terri Schiavo of her humanity. He and those who support him, therefore, act on a prejudice against her physical condition that leads them to dehumanize her, much like the racists whose similar prejudices led them to disregard the humanity of black Americans. Some argue that his decision is legal, because under Florida law an individual may refuse nutrition by artificial means. Against this there is the legal objection that it has never been proven beyond a reasonable doubt that Terri Schiavo did in fact signify such a wish. There is also the constitutional objection based on the fact that the Florida State constitution refers to the right to enjoy and defend life as "inalienable," which means that under no circumstances can it be transferred or surrendered. As it guarantees the security of the right, it also limits the freedom of those who enjoy such rights, which cannot be surrendered by any legal or other means. This concept was, by the way, critical to the argument used by such philosophers as John Locke to refute the notion that legitimate government could be based on a right of conquest, i.e., tyrannical coercion. Legitimate government requires consent. Those who submit to authority under the threat of force (submit or be killed) cannot be said to consent because neither side of the bargain (submit or be killed) involves free choice: On the one hand, subjection against their will, on the other surrender of a right (to life) which, being inalienable, is not theirs to give. The conqueror cannot acquire authority in exchange for not doing what he can never be granted the right to do. Cf. John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government, Chapter XIV: "'And this judgment they cannot part with, it being out of a man's power so to submit himself to another as to give him a liberty to destroy him, God and nature never allowing a man so to abandon himself as to neglect his own preservation; and since he cannot take away his own life, neither can he give another power to take it." Americans should reflect long and hard on the import of this argument before they surrender to the sirens' song of self-destruction coming from those who advocate a right to suicide.

[8]  In Federalist 81, when Hamilton lists the safeguards against "judiciary encroachments on the legislative authority" he cites in particular "its total incapacity to support its usurpations by force." Accepting the notion that judicial orders, at any level, may constitute an executive authority superior to the chief executive would give the judiciary just such a forceful capacity. When every judicial decision carries the implied threat of armed insurrection, a key safeguard of liberty and self-government is removed. Sadly, governor Jeb Bush of Florida is likely to become a proverbial illustration of the dangerously enervating effect this must have on the energy of the Executive branch, and its ability to defend the rights of the people and their representatives.


(The above is a revised version of an article that first appeared at WorldNetDaily on Mar. 24, 2005, titled "Why Jeb Bush has the power to act now.")







RENEWAMERICA.us  -  Home  -  News  -  Columns  -  Alan Keyes column  -  Keyes Archives  -  Message Board